Hobbes
|
Descartes
|
Tennessee Philosophical Association |
Join
TPA |
Current Conference and Call for Papers | Past Conferences | Past and Current Presidents | Philosophical Associations and Reference Resources |
Tennessee Philosophical Association
47th Annual Meeting: Oct. 30-31, 2015
Vanderbilt University
Keynote
Speaker:
Susan Wolf, The
University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill
Aesthetic Responsibility
Philosophers often distinguish between causal responsibility and moral responsibility, taking the latter to be an important mark of our distinctive humanity. But focusing exclusively on the attitudes and judgments we form toward people on the basis of their moral characters and behavior leads us to overly narrow conceptions both of responsibility and of our humanity.
As a corrective, this paper considers the attitudes and judgments we make of artists on the basis of their artworks, suggesting that there is such a thing as aesthetic responsibility that is both similar to and different from moral responsibility. I conclude with some thoughts about what a consideration of aesthetic responsibility tells us more generally about the concepts of responsibility and humanity.
Friday, 7:30 P.M., 114 Furman Hall, followed by a spirited reception
Sessions: Saturday, Furman Hall
9:00 am through 5:00 pm
9:00 – 9:55
Epistemic Reasons and the Problem of
the Criterion
Andrew Cling (University
of Alabama Huntsville)
Response: Scott Aikin (Vanderbilt University)
Furman 007
Consequential Mistakes in the Debate
Over Kidney Sales
Luke Semrau (Vanderbilt
University)
Response: Rebecca Tuvel (Rhodes College)
Furman 106
Kant and the Ground(s) of Dignity
Andy Britton (Georgia
State University)
Response: Julian Wuerth (Vanderbilt University)
Furman 109
Theories of
Personal Identity:
Biological Continuity vs. Brain-Realized Psychological Continuity
Andrew Naylor (Indiana
University South Bend)
Response: Alejandro Arango (Vanderbilt University)
Furman 209
10:00 - 10:55
Psychological Readings of Kant’s
Second Analogy and the Representation of Causality
Andrew Roche (Centre
College)
Response: Fiacha Heneghan (Vanderbilt University)
Furman 007
Montaigne’s Essays and/as
Pyrrhonian Skepticism
Brian Ribeiro (University
of Tennessee Chattanooga)
Response: Darla Migan (Vanderbilt University)
Furman 106
Adaptive Preferences and Respect
Steven Weimer (Arkansas
State University)
Response: Sabeen Ahmed (Vanderbilt University)
Furman 109
An Argument Against Jennifer Lackey’s
Deflationary View of Group Testimony
Chris Lucibella
(University of Memphis)
Response: Tempest Henning (Vanderbilt University)
Furman 209
11:00 – 11:55
Naturalism in Neo-Aristotelian Virtue
Ethics: What It Is and Why It Matters
Boomer Trujillo (Vanderbilt University)
Response: Jordan Corwin (University of Notre Dame)
Furman 007
Explaining Political Authority
Chris King (Miami
University)
Response: Austin Kippes (University of Tennessee at Chattanooga)
Furman 106
Truthmaking and Divine Simplicity
Allen Gehring (Brescia
University)
Response: Rick Ray (Northeast State Community College)
Furman 109
The Problem of Truth:
Expressivism, Pragmatism and Moral Disagreement
Scott Aikin and Michael
Hodges (Vanderbilt University)
Response: Mark Michael (Austin Peay State University)
Furman 209
12:00-12:05
Business Meeting –
Election of President and Secretary
Furman 109
12:05-1:25
Lunch (On Your Own)
1:30-2:25
The Possibility of an Aristotelian
Realism
Gary Jaeger (Vanderbilt
University)
Response: Matt Congdon (Vanderbilt University)
Furman 007
The Normativity of Love
Mark Hopwood (Sewanee: The University of the South)
Response: Rick Ray (Northeast State Community College)
Furman 106
Moral Responsibility and the Ethics
of Belief
Alexander Bozzo (Marquette
University)
Response: Brian Ribeiro (University of Tennessee Chattanooga)
Furman 109
Silence and Abortion: Do Women
Deserve Better?
Amy McKiernan (Vanderbilt
University)
Response: Tyler Colwell (University of Memphis)
Furman 209
2:30-3:25
Is Environmentalism Antidemocratic?:
Pragmatism and Non-anthropocentrism in Environmental Thought
Mark Michael (Austin Peay
State University)
Response: Mark Coppenger (Southern Baptist Theological Seminary)
Furman 007
Why Peirce’s Anti-Foundationalism Is
Not Anti-Cartesian
Thomas Dabay (Vanderbilt
University)
Response: Andrew Cling (University of Alabama Huntsville)
Furman 106
Finitude and Infinity in Ethics
Michael Brodrick (Arkansas
Tech University)
Response: Michael Hodges (Vanderbilt University)
Furman 109
Finalism in Spinoza’s Physics?
Norman Whitman (Rhodes
College)
Response: Terry Boyd (Vanderbilt University)
Furman 209
Legal Ethical Love:
Another model of recognition through Hegel’s account of Marriage
Elizabeth Lanphier
(Vanderbilt University)
Response: Peter Capretto (Vanderbilt University)
Furman 217
3:30-5:00
AUTHOR MEETS CRITICS:
Civil Disobedience in Global Perspective
Author: Michael Allen (East Tennessee State University)
Critical Replies from: Amber Carlson and Shannon Fyfe (Vanderbilt
University)
Furman 007
AUTHOR MEETS CRITICS:
Expressing the
Inexpressible in Lyotard and Pseudo-Dionysus
Author: Mélanie Walton
(Belmont University)
Critical Replies from: Alyssa Lowery and Darla Migan (Vanderbilt
University)
Furman 106
AUTHOR MEETS CRITICS: Starting with
Mill
Author: John Fitzpatrick
(University of Tennessee Chattanooga)
Critical Replies from: Boomer Trujillo and Lyn Radke (Vanderbilt
University)
Furman 109
Abstracts of papers
In addition to the papers listed below, we will also be having three “Author Meets Critics” sessions this year, each involving two critical commentaries and a prepared response from the author. Please see the conference schedule for further details on those sessions.
Scott Aikin
and Michael Hodges (Vanderbilt University)
“The Problem of Truth: Expressivism, Pragmatism and Moral Disagreement”
This paper is a brief
overview of the motivations for expressivism and a presentation of a
disagreement problem for expressivism. We present a pragmatist solution to
the problem of disagreement and outline its consequences.
Alexander
Bozzo (Marquette University)
“Moral Responsibility and the Ethics of Belief”
William K. Clifford famously declared, "[I]t is is wrong always, everywhere, and
for anyone, to believe anything upon insufficient evidence." There are few that
have been willing to defend the spirit, let alone the letter, of Clifford's
ethics of belief. In this paper, I defend a moderate version of Clifford's
ethics of belief.
Andy Britton
(The University of Memphis)
“Kant and the Ground(s) of Dignity”
In the Groundwork, Kant famously claims that autonomy is the ground of dignity.
Here, I argue that this explanation is incomplete. When considered within the
context of Kant's larger (practical) project, and particularly the discussion of
transcendental freedom, it becomes clear that the ‘fact of reason’ is necessary
if dignity is to be adequately grounded in autonomy. However, as is well known,
Kant's employment of the fact of reason is extremely controversial and dismissed
by many, while his conception of dignity seems to invite less criticism. Thus, I
attempt to show that accepting the fact of reason is necessary for preserving
Kant's conception of dignity.
Michael
Brodrick (Miami University)
“Finitude and Infinity in Ethics”
Pragmatism’s moral legacy rests on the assumption that we are finite.
Unfortunately, both James and Dewey were ambivalent about human finitude. Much
of their work presupposes that we are inherently limited, but it is not hard to
find in their writings passages that suggest in no uncertain terms that our
limits are not as inevitable as they seem. Dewey sometimes articulated an
ambitious form of meliorism that threatens the ethics of tolerance at the heart
of the pragmatist movement. Amelioration can be tragically delayed or even
reversed if we embrace infinite ambitions. But there is hope in that James
suggested a modest form of meliorism that supports an ethics of tolerance.
Andrew Cling
(University of Alabama Huntsville)
“Epistemic Reasons and the Problem of the Criterion”
The problem of the
criterion is a skeptical paradox about the role that criteria of truth play in
knowledge: to know we need a criterion but to have a criterion we need
knowledge. Chisholm does not quite get the problem right: he states it in two
different ways but favors the one that makes it a problem about epistemic
knowledge, not about knowledge per se. But the problem is not just about
epistemic knowledge. Nor is it just about knowledge. It is about the
relationship between epistemic values and the right kinds of epistemic reasons.
Skepticism casts a broad net.
Thomas Dabay
(Vanderbilt University)
“Why Peirce’s Anti-Foundationalism Is Not Anti-Cartesian”
A close reading of Descartes’ Regulae ad Directionem Ingenii and Peirce’s
“Questions Concerning Certain Faculties Claimed for Man” and “Some Consequences
of Four Incapacities” calls into question the common interpretation of Peirce as
being anti- Cartesian. In particular, Descartes’ conception of intuition differs
from Peirce’s, and on one plausible reading of Descartes his intuitionism
actually mirrors Peirce’s inferentialism in key respects. These similarities
between Descartes and Peirce should make us rethink the narratives developed
around Peirce and pragmatism more generally.
Allen Gehring
(Brescia University)
“Truthmaking and Divine Simplicity”
Recently, philosophers
have argued that the notion of truthmaking is required to understand divine
simplicity. An important issue overlooked here regards truthbearers.
I contend the truthmaking account of divine simplicity is implausible, because
it is committed to the view that the only truthbearers are human beliefs.
Mark Hopwood
(Sewanee: The University of the South)
“The Normativity of Love”
In this paper, I argue that love is distinguished from both reason and desire by
the kind of normative demand that it imposes on the lover. To love something is
not merely to desire it, but to recognize it as setting a standard for one’s
desires (and thus one’s life more broadly). This standard is not, however, one
that need be taken to apply to anyone else who does not share a love of the same
object. I develop this thesis by considering two examples of loving beauty: in a
work of art, and in one’s newborn child.
Gary Jaeger
(Vanderbilt University)
“The Possibility of an Aristotelian Realism”
Some metaethical realists
have unsuccessfully turned to Aristotle to develop a form of realism that can
overcome standard objections to realism. While one of these attempts has
successfully diagnosed realism’s problematic notion of objectivity that too
sharply distinguishes mind from world, none of them have successfully explained
how subjectively inflected reasons can meet the standards of realism. I
argue that Aristotle’s own distinction between theoretical and practical
reasoning provides the resources needed to see how facts about the mind can be
objective enough to provide us with reasons that meet the standards of realism
Chris King
(Miami University)
“Explaining Political Authority”
This paper argues that hypothetical consent theory (HCT) is superior to actual
consent theory (ACT) as an explanation of political authority. Indeed, it is
superior as an explanation of authority for the familiar reason that even if
political authority exists, persons do not typically consent to it. More
surprisingly, perhaps, HCT turns out to be more theoretically powerful than ACT
with respect to political authority for roughly the same reasons one might
ordinarily think that ACT is theoretically powerful in cases of actual but
non-political consent. This is because the cost to others of failing to meet
reasonable public expectations serves as grounds for the creation and
particularization of duties in both cases.
Elizabeth
Lanphier (Vanderbilt University)
“Legal Ethical Love: Another model of recognition through Hegel’s account of
Marriage”
This paper offers another model of Hegelian recognition through a reading of
Hegel’s depiction of marriage from the Philosophy of Right. The marital
structure has three key features that enhance an understanding of recognition.
First, it is a real place from which to think and learn about recognition.
Second, marriage as Hegel describes conforms to the shape of absolute infinity.
Finally, this model is one that calls upon the imagination as a key step in
recognition. The form of recognition modeled in Hegel’s account of marriage is
one that demands a space for reflection and imagining anew.
Chris
Lucibella (University of Memphis)
“An Argument Against Jennifer Lackey’s Deflationary View of Group Testimony”
In this paper, I offer an
argument against Jennifer Lackey's 2014 article “A Deflationary Account of Group
Testimony.” There, she defends what she refers to as a deflationary account of
group testimony, which holds that we ought not consider groups as able to give
testimony apart from the constituent members of the group. In the interest of
preserving a notion of group testimony in which groups can be considered
testifiers apart from their members, I argue that there is ample reason to
reject Lackey's deflationary account, as it relies on under-theorized premises.
Amy McKiernan
(Vanderbilt University)
“Silence and Abortion: Do Women Deserve Better?”
Feminists for Life (FFL)
does not blame women for abortion. The non-profit locates itself within feminist
movements using historically feminist language and images. How, then, might a
feminist philosopher who values access to safe and legal abortion respond? I
argue that although members of FFL claim to care for women, they actually
silence women by reducing them to the victims of abortion. Their language does
not explicitly condemn women, yet it restricts the agency of a speaker so
severely that it makes a woman’s speech about her own needs and desires nearly
impossible for others to hear and affirm.
Mark Michael
(Austin Peay State University)
“Is Environmentalism Antidemocratic?: Pragmatism and Non-anthropocentrism in
Environmental Thought”
Environmental pragmatists like Bryan Norton and Ben Minteer have a deep mistrust
of environmental non-anthropocentrists like Baird Callicott, Holmes Rolston, and
Laura Westra in terms of the depth of their commitment to democratic theory and
majority rule. Norton goes so far as to suggest that the two views are mutually
incompatible. In this paper I ask whether that is correct. The answer depends on
how these views are cashed out, but I argue that these views are incompatible
only if one ascribes to them extreme and consequently implausible claims. In
fact on a natural interpretation of these views they share a significant amount
of common ground. They are most likely to disagree over the fairly narrow albeit
important issue of whether nature or non-humans can have rights or be
significantly harmed. But unless one’s answer to this question is taken as
critical for whether one is a democrat or an environmentalist, the two views are
not mutually incompatible.
Andrew Naylor
(Indiana University South Bend)
“Theories of Personal Identity: Biological Continuity vs. Brain-Realized
Psychological Continuity”
What I take to be the best
extant version of the psychological continuity theory of personal identity over
time requires psychological continuity to be reliably caused by processes
occurring entirely within the brain. While this version of the theory can handle
a formidable objection of Parfit’s, it falters when confronted with a certain
situation where a cerebral hemisphere of one person is implanted in the
decerebrate body of another person. An alternative biological continuity theory
can handle such a situation but faces an analogous problem of its own. I offer a
further consideration that favors the biological continuity theory.
Brian Ribeiro
(University of Tennessee Chattanooga)
“Montaigne’s Essays and/as Pyrrhonian Skepticism”
In this paper I explore a Pyrrhonian reading of Montaigne’s Essays. I
ask, first, how does Montaigne understand Pyrrhonism, and, second, how does
Montaigne’s Pyrrhonian allegiance invite us to understand his project in writing
the Essays?
Andrew Roche
(Centre College)
“Psychological Readings of Kant’s Second Analogy and the Representation of
Causality”
“Psychological readings” of Kant’s Second Analogy in his Critique of Pure
Reason construe him as arguing that one must represent an event to be caused
if one is to experience an event at all. This contrasts with epistemological
readings that take Kant to be concerned about our justification for believing
that events have occurred. There is good reason to adopt the psychological
reading, but in this paper I contend that it is prima facie difficult to
see how Kant plausibly introduces the representation of causality into his
argument, so construed. I consider three proposals and contend that a hybrid of
all three is required.
Luke Semrau
(Vanderbilt University)
“Consequential Mistakes in the Debate Over Kidney Sales?”
That vendors would be harmed is a perennial objection to kidney markets, and is
particularly acute for those who defend sales on consequentialist grounds.
Julian Koplin has recently offered an empirically informed defense of the claim
that vendors will be significantly harmed even in well-regulated markets. I
argue that Koplin’s opposition evinces a failure of imagination. Problems he
claims insoluble are not. Koplin’s argument is further undermined by the fact
that he misunderstands consequentialism. So as to not make things worse for
those who are already badly off, we should regulate, not prohibit kidney
markets.
Boomer
Trujillo (Vanderbilt University)
“Naturalism in Neo-Aristotelian Virtue Ethics: What It Is and Why It Matters”
Some neo-Aristotelian virtue ethicists tout their theories as naturalistic.
However, what naturalism means and why it matters are unclear. This paper serves
two purposes. First, it attempts to categorize naturalism in neo-Aristotelian
virtue ethics by listing six necessary features. Second, it closes with a note
on why it matters. It argues that naturalism characterizes a theoretical
world-view that demands an ethical theory be connected with political and moral
life.
Steven Weimer
(Arkansas State University)
“Adaptive Preferences and Respect”
Although the concept of adaptive preferences is regarded by many as an essential
tool for diagnosing and combatting injustice, its critics allege that use of the
concept disrespects those who are taken to hold such preferences. Rosa Terlazzo
has recently developed a novel account of adaptive preferences which she claims
shows appropriate respect for persons while remaining an effective political
tool. Against this claim, I argue that there is an important form of respect
which her account neither recognizes nor provides. I argue further that the
revised version of Terlazzo’s account I propose remedies this shortcoming while
remaining politically efficacious.
Norman
Whitman (Rhodes College)
“Finalism in Spinoza’s Physics?”
Despite Baruch Spinoza’s
assertions that his philosophy and Nature in general has no final causes, Alan
Gabbey presents a compelling case that Spinoza’s physics may rely on a subtle
form of finalism. According to Gabbey, Spinoza presents a confused
understanding of simple bodies that requires, what Gabbey calls, the Principle
of Least Modal Mutation (PLMM) to make sense of their motion. In
opposition to Gabbey, I will show how Spinoza’s understanding of simple bodies
does not entail an extrinsic principle of organization but rather requires a
dynamic and immanent understanding of bodily action whereby bodies produce one
another in a non-teleological manner.
A map and directions to Furman Hall are available on the Vanderbilt Website. You will need to click the "Back" button to return to the TPAWeb site after you go to Vandy's map and directions to Furman Hall.
We thank Pellissippi State for hosting this web site.
Last updated